[1] The "pacific mandate" does not apply to Lutherans.
Neither does it apply to Christians. If that were the case,
it'd be shocking. In truth, of course, God's mandate of
peace, of just peacemaking, applies to all people and
peoples. It pertains then to all Christian saints who,
simultaneously as sinners and as creatures, stand under it.
[2] God's "pacific mandate" surely pertains therefore to
Lutherans, though not only to Lutherans. But, to say "not
only" to Lutherans, while true in a technical sense, implies,
"We're no different from anyone else. Why single us out?"
Lutherans, however, should be singled out. Indeed, I pray
that God would single us out for the "pacific," lest we again,
sadly, neglect its pertinence. In this way, then, the pacific is
our mandate.
[3] It's time. Ponder the pacific. Our kairos has
come! And pondering it, I'm convinced we'll discern a more
vigorous pacific vocation. Isn't ELCA Presiding Bishop Mark
Hanson getting at precisely that in his "President's Address" at
the Lutheran World Federation's 2004 Council Meeting? "In our
violent and war-torn world, let us as the LWF deepen our resolve to
. . . together develop principles for a just peace that become as
defining of us as have been the principles of just
war.1"
[4] Thus far, Bishop Hanson is quite right. Let's radicalize
the Bishop's point, just a little. Just peace is the first
principle of the just war tradition.2 Indeed, as first
principle just peace must normatively be the first priority, the
overriding presumption of the just war tradition. Just
peacemaking must not be hid under a bushel basket. But, let's
radicalize the Bishop's point even more. As just peacemaking
more firmly defines Lutherans, let's deepen our resolve that just
peacemaking be more defining of our governments. I'm sure
this would be a friendly amendment to Bishop Hanson's motion.
Still, let's radicalize the Bishop's point a third time. As
just peacemaking more firmly defines Lutherans, let's deepen our
resolve that just peacemaking be more defining of our economies,
our civil society, our families, our . . . ; well, you get the
picture.
[5] I'll consider Bishop Hanson's point in three steps.
First, I will examine the "pacific presumption" of the just war
tradition, a presumption routinely ignored. Second, I will
explore in Luther a "pacific partiality" for just peacemaking
practice. Third, I will suggest five ways that Lutherans
might imagine a unified theory and practice of just peacemaking in
hope of a "pacific proliferation" of Lutheran public
vocation. Characteristically, Lutherans confess Christ's
freedom making, proclaimed in the Gospel by the Holy Spirit as the
church catholic's vocational bonding to God's world for God's
world.
I. Pacific Presumption
[6] God's "pacific mandate" establishes just peacemaking as the
just war tradition's basic presumption. Lutherans often
forget this, precisely the forgetfulness that stands behind Bishop
Hanson's appeal. On the one hand, Lutherans
characteristically stand within the just war tradition. We do
so confessionally and rightly.3 On the other
hand, we need a much, much better understanding of this
tradition.4 Without better
understanding, we'll get exploited, again.
[7] Think "Thou shalt not kill" as the first commandment of the
"just war tradition." At first that thought might seem
patently unwarranted. After all, war is always about killing,
even when justifiably undertaken and prosecuted using "just war
tradition5"
criteria. War either violates God's commandment or falls
outside the commandment's purview when constrained under certain
criteria. In his Large Catechism, Martin Luther
takes the latter position: "Therefore neither God nor the
government is included in this commandment, nor is their right to
take human life abrogated.6"
[8] Contrary to popular opinion, just war tradition takes God's
"not kill" command as its basic presupposition. By grounding
itself upon a strong underlying presumption against war, just war
tradition advocates restraint and admonishes any neglect of this
presumption. Luther even encodes this presumption in the very title
of his 1527 treatise, Whether Soldiers, Too, Can Be
Saved7. When made
explicit, this presumption paradoxically strengthens Luther's
insight that God exempts government from this commandment's
prohibition.
[9] During its first three centuries the church addressed ever
more forthrightly the question of whether war can be justified in
view of God's "not kill" command.8 Church fathers treated
the question of war within the social contexts of their times and
in light of both the teachings of Jesus and the Ten Commandments,
with the former receiving the bulk of attention. Some, like
Athanasius in To Amun, treat war with reference to God's
"not kill" command.
One is not supposed to kill, but killing the enemy in battle is both lawful and praiseworthy. For this reason individuals who have distinguished themselves in war are considered worthy of great honors, and monuments are put up to celebrate their accomplishments. Thus, at one particular time, and under one set of circumstances, an act is not permitted, but when the time and conditions are right, it is both allowed and condoned.9
Both Augustine and Aquinas broach the question of justifiable
war in their treatments of God's "not kill" command.10
[10] Luther moves beyond Athanasius's vague "but when the time and
conditions are right" by using arguments drawn principally from
Augustine, whom Aquinas and Calvin also follow. Augustine
claims that God's "not kill" command "allows certain exceptions"
because God can indeed authorize killing.11 Aquinas puts it
succinctly: "God has sovereign authority over life and death . . .
.12" God's
authority, then, authorizes political authority to put criminals to
death and to wage war at God's bidding.
[11] Luther employs a twofold hermeneutic when he composes the
catechetical meaning of the succinct yet comprehensive Fifth
Commandment in his Small Catechism: "We are to fear and
love God, so that we neither endanger nor harm the lives of our
neighbors, but instead help and support them in all of life's
needs.13" First, "not
kill" is a synecdoche that proscribes all violence whatsoever
toward humans. The succinct "not kill" becomes
comprehensive. Second, "not kill" includes a tacit
affirmative which begins with Luther's "but." Notice again
the comprehensiveness of Luther's explicit affirmative.
[12] Luther drives this point home in his Large
Catechism. First, the force of the "not": "God wants to
have everyone defended, delivered, and protected from the
wickedness and violence of others and he has placed this
commandment as a wall, fortress, and refuge around our neighbors,
so that no one may do them bodily harm or injury." Next the
force of the tacit, comprehensive affirmative:
[T]his commandment is violated not only when we do evil, but also when we have the opportunity to do good to our neighbors and to prevent, protect, and save them from suffering bodily harm or injury, but fail to do so. If you send a naked person away when you could clothe him, you have let him freeze to death. If you see anyone who is suffering from hunger and do not feed her, you have let her starve. Likewise, if you see anyone who is condemned to death or in similar peril and do not save him although you have means and ways to do so, you have killed him. It will be of no help for you to use the excuse that you did not assist their deaths by word or deed, for you have withheld your love from them and robbed them of the kindness by means of which their lives might have been saved.
[13] Therefore God rightly calls all persons murderers who do not offer counsel or assistance to those in need and peril of body and life. He will pass a most terrible sentence upon them at the Last Day, as Christ himself declares[Matt. 25:42-43].14 The negative form of the commandment places a comprehensive, protective boundary around our physical life. The tacit affirmative sets in motion a comprehensive, life-generating bonding-and-bridging into the physical life of neighbors. The entire scriptures teach this tacit and comprehensive affirmative, notes Luther.15 In this way God's Fifth Commandment establishes the "presumption" of just peacemaking thereby authorizing the "pacific mandate."
II. Pacific Partiality
[14] Why, then, do many get the impression that Luther appears
more partial to war than to peace? Or, using Bishop Hanson's
expression, why does Luther seem more defined by just war
principles than by just peacemaking principles. The simplest
explanation is that people often asked Luther about matters of war
and he replied.
[15] In response Luther argues three points-of course he said
other things as well. First, political authority rightfully
bears "the sword" because it serves as a "mask of God."
Christians, therefore, may exercise offices of political authority
as their vocation. A Christian can be a prince, for
instance. Second, just war tradition categorically prohibits
expansionist wars of desire. Third, just war tradition
categorically prohibits holy war/crusade.16 We'll look only
at the first point because the prince who bears "the sword" in one
hand must bear "the scepter" in the other. And God shapes
"the scepter" according to just peace. This is the "mirror
for the prince," which Luther holds up. Mask and mirror,
sword and scepter.
[16] Mask and Sword. Luther's critical theology of
political authority emerges over the full course of his life.
Many, though not all, of its basic features are already in place in
his 1523 well-known treatise, Temporal Authority: To What
Extent It Should Be Obeyed17 (LW 45,
81-129). Luther addresses particular questions put to
him by John the Steadfast, his soon-to-be prince. Now that he
had become an ardent defender of the evangelical cause, John
inquired of Luther whether he would be able to exercise the full
range of powers of the princely office with a good Christian
conscience. John was concerned specifically about the power
of "the sword," the coercive power of last resort that belongs in
an exceptional way to political authority.18 Some Anabaptist
sectarians were perturbing John with certain Bible passages like
"do not resist an evildoer" (Matt. 5:39), "never avenge yourselves
. . . vengeance is mine, I will repay, says the Lord" (Rom. 12:19),
and "do not repay evil for evil" (1Pet. 3:9). Such texts,
claimed the Anabaptists, preclude all true Christian, including
those occupying the office of prince, from exercising "the sword"
either in a criminal court proceeding in order to keep the peace or
analogously in a justifiable war. Luther, like Augustine,
draws the analogy between criminal peacekeeping and just war
peacekeeping.
[17] Luther also had to counter the normative medieval
interpretation of passages like those from the Sermon on the
Mount. According to that interpretation, a prince could bear
"the sword" and remain a Christian in good conscience because these
teachings applied only to those who were specifically dedicated to
"Christian perfection," namely, members of a monastic order or the
sacerdotal priesthood. Accordingly, princes need not be held
accountable to such high "counsels of perfection," since they,
being lay, remained "common" Christians. Luther roundly
rejected such scholastic, interpretive "wantonness and
caprice." Among Christians there exists no external "class"
distinction between the perfect and the common based on status
markers like "outwardly male or female, prince or peasant, monk or
layman" (LW, 45, 88). Here, Luther's doctrine of
vocation comes into play. Passages, such as those from the
Sermon on the Mount, "apply to everyone alike" (LW, 45,
88).
[18] A second historical factor situates Luther's
reflections. In his earlier 1520 treatise, To the
Christian Nobility of the German Nation, Luther appealed to
the Christian nobility as laypeople to take the reform of the
church into their own hands, since the German bishops had not.
Luther noted that the political authority of rulers was not
delegated to them hierarchically from the church and its bishops,
as the dominant heritage of papal political theology held.
His provocative assessment of political authority left many
wondering whether, by so emancipating political authority from the
church, he had ascribed unlimited, totalitarian powers to political
authority. Could princes, with legitimate authority, command
as God's will "whatever they please"? And correspondingly,
were their subjects "bound to obey their rulers in everything" as
they would obey God's will (LW, 45, 83)? Luther
addressed this question in part two of Temporal
Authority. He stakes out the extent and limits of
political authority and its power of the sword (LW, 45,
104). According to Luther, political authority has no
authorization to coerce faith. In this way, the subtitle of his
treatise is telling: To What Extent It Should Be
Obeyed! In part three Luther offers his own practical
advice concerning the use of the prince's office in a Christian
manner. His remarks bear the stamp of a political layperson's
imagination, as he himself acknowledges.
[19] Luther begins part one by citing Romans 13:1-2 and 1 Peter
2:13-14. These texts authenticate the constitution of
political authority's obligation of "the sword" as "a godly estate"
(LW, 45, 87) and thereby testify that God is the primary
agent behind "the law of this temporal sword" (LW, 45,
86).19 Luther argues
that Gen. 4:14-15 and 9:5-6 strengthen the first two texts by
emphasizing that the law of the political sword has "existed from
the beginning of the world," after the Fall. Luther
interprets, for example, Gen. 9:5 in light of the Decalogue's "not
kill" command and Gen. 9:6 in relation to God's establishment of
political authority with its power of "the sword" (LW 2,
139-141). God has found ways to inscribe this law into human
community from the beginning of time, even though, he notes,
communities have also found ways to have this divine work of the
sword "not carried out." The famous lex talionis of
Exod. 21:23-25, along with verse 14, certifies that Moses
"confirmed" this inscribed-from-the-beginning law of the political
sword. Matthew 26:52 and Luke 3:14 also "confirm" it.
Luther's conclusion: "Hence, it is certain and clear enough that it
is God's will that the temporal sword and law be used for the
punishment of the wicked and the protection of the upright"
(LW, 45, 87). 1 Peter 2:14 (LW, 45, 86) and
Rom. 13:3 (LW, 45, 91) warrant preventing wickedness and
promoting uprightness, the twofold criterion of God's will
regarding the full range of political authority, including its
power of "the sword."
[20] Luther argues that, because of humanity's condition, God
constitutes the full horizon of the first use of the law in general
and political authority with its coercive sword. Humanity is
composed of both righteous Christians and the unrighteous.
Righteous Christians hear and trust the voice of Christ; thus the
Holy Spirit works through their agency, directing the righteous to
do right and bear wrong. By the Spirit, therefore,
righteous Christians "do of their own accord much more than all
laws and teachings can demand, just as Paul says in 1 Timothy
1[:9], 'The law is not laid down for the just but for the lawless'"
(LW, 45, 89). Throughout Luther's career, 1 Tim.1:9
remained a hermeneutically significant text.20 Accordingly, God
constitutes the law not with righteous Christians in
view.
[21] Luther was always keen to recognize that many baptized
Christians are so in name only and thus waste the Holy Spirit's
agency for conducting their lives in love of neighbor.
"Christians are few and far between (as the saying is)"
(LW, 45, 91). Luther numbers such false Christians
among the unrighteous. The unrighteous, readily in the
majority by Luther's calculus, live without the Spirit of Christ as
the core agent of their lives and thus "need the law to instruct,
constrain, and compel them to do good21" (LW, 45,
89). Luther remains a wide-eyed realist about sin and
evil. He equally remains a wide-eyed realist about the triune
God's creational resolve to contest against sin and evil for the
sake of creation! For this reason God has provided them [the
unrighteous] a different government beyond the Christian estate and
kingdom of God. He has subjected them to the sword so that,
even though they would like to, they are unable to practice their
wickedness, and if they do practice it they cannot do so without
fear or with success and impunity. (LW, 45, 90) This
is the sword that serves as dike and remedy against sin
(remedium peccati). In Whether Soldiers Too Can
Be Saved Luther enlarges the sword to include a justified
war. For the very fact that the sword has been instituted by
God to punish the evil, protect the good, and preserve peace (Rom.
13:1-4; 1 Pet. 2:13-14) is powerful and sufficient proof that war
and killing along with all the things that accompany wartime and
martial law have been instituted by God. (LW, 46,
95)
[22] Luther's realism about sin and evil leads him to reflect on
possible relationships of power wherein the "wolves, lions, [and]
eagles"-the hoarders and inhibitors of God's temporal, creational
banquet-among us (LW, 45, 92) would simply "devour" the
"sheep" (LW, 45, 91)-the most vulnerable among us and, indeed, all
of us in our vulnerabilities. If such a lax situation
persists, temporal life and flourishing would eventually be
"reduced to chaos" (LW, 45, 91). Always mindful of
oppressive and violent wickedness, the triune God constitutes two
modes of governing the world, each with its own integrity with
regard to divine purpose and power: "the spiritual, by which the
Holy Spirit produces Christians and righteous people under Christ;
and the temporal, which restrains the un-Christian and wicked so
that-no thanks to them-they are obliged to keep still and to
maintain an outward peace" (LW, 45, 91). Here Luther
employs his comprehensive, remarkably enduring, and fruitful
distinction between law and gospel with its accompanying
distinction between the triune God's two ways of ruling the world,
often referred to as Luther's two-kingdoms teaching.22
[23] Following Augustine, Luther notes that even the sword is a
temporal work of love.
Now slaying and robbing do not seem to be works of love. A simple man therefore does not think it is a Christian thing to do. In truth, however, even this is a work of love. . . . [W]hen I think of a soldier fulfilling his office by punishing the wicked, killing the wicked, and creating so much misery, it seems an un-Christian work completely contrary to Christian love. But when I think of how it protects the good and keeps and preserves wife and child, house and farm, property, and honor and peace, then I see how precious and godly this work is; and I observe that it amputates a leg or a hand, so that the whole body may not perish. . . .
What men write about war, saying that it is a great plague, is all true. But they should also consider how great the plague is that war prevents. (LW, 46, 96)23
[24] Luther's view of the integrity of political authority under
God critically distinguishes his theological reflection from both
the papal theology of his time and the sectarian account of
political authority. Given the divinely constituted integrity
of both governments, "it is out of the question" that Christians
should attempt to govern the whole world or even a single country
by the kind of non-coercive, free and freeing spiritual governance
of the gospel (LW, 45, 91, 93, 107-108). For this
reason, there exists a special Christian vocation that "carefully
distinguish[es] between these two governments. Both must be
permitted to remain; the one to produce righteousness, the other to
bring about external peace and prevent evil deeds. Neither
one is sufficient in the world without the other" (LW, 45,
92).
[25] Jesus and the Pacifist Question. Readied with this
"both" kingdoms hermeneutic, Luther turns to the significance of
Jesus' Sermon on the Mount. Christians are to have no
recourse to civil law or to political authority's sword in two
types of circumstances: "among themselves" (LW, 45, 92,
94) and "by and for themselves" (LW, 45, 94). First,
within their community Christians are not to seek recourse in the
law or in the sword of political authority. Second,
Christians have no need for the sword if what is at stake is only
their own well-being (LW, 45, 95). The second
circumstance flows from another basic distinction in Luther's
construal of the relationship of Christians to the sword: the
distinction between self and neighbor.
[26] Since a true Christian lives and labors on earth not for
himself alone but for his neighbor, he does by the very nature of
his spirit even what he himself has no need of, but is needful and
useful to his neighbor. Because the sword is most beneficial
and necessary for the whole world in order to preserve peace,
punish sin, and restrain the wicked, the Christian submits most
willingly to the rule of the sword, pays his taxes, honors those in
authority, serves, helps, and does all he can to assist governing
authority, that it may continue to function and be held in honor
and fear. Although he has no need of these things for
himself-to him they are not essential-nevertheless, he concerns
himself about what is serviceable and of benefit to others, as Paul
teaches in Ephesians 5 (LW, 45, 94).24
[27] Luther views political authority itself as wholly an office
"on behalf of others" (LW, 46, 122). A prince who
corrupts his office by exercising political authority in order "to
rejoice in his [own] power and wealth and honor, . . . [t]hat kind
of prince would start a war over an empty nut and think nothing but
satisfying his own will" (ibid.). Luther argues that
these three sets of distinctions-between the triune God's two ways
of ruling, between church and world, and between self and
neighbor-bring "into harmony" the two sets of biblical texts that
on the surface appear contradictory. On the one hand,
Christians do not resist evil with the sword either among
themselves or for their own survival or gain. On the other
hand, Christians are "under obligation to serve and assist the
sword by whatever means [they] can, with body, goods, honor, and
soul" in order to resist evil when oppressors afflict others.
"For [the sword] is something which you do not need, but which is
very beneficial and essential for the whole world and for your
neighbor"; indeed, "[t]he world cannot and dare not dispense with
it" (LW, 45, 95). By so serving and assisting even
the sword, "in what concerns the person or property of others,"
argues Luther, "you govern yourself according to love and tolerate
no injustice toward your neighbor" (LW, 45, 96).
[28] Christians participate in the whole panoply of the civil use
of the law and, more narrowly, in the office of political
authority, including its coercive and restraining sword, because
these exist as God's own "work and creation" (LW, 45,
99). They are God's "masks" (larvae dei) for creating and
sustaining the temporal life of the world (LW, 45, 96-100;
also LW 14, 112-123; and LW 26, 94-96). "For the hand that
wields this sword and kills with it is not man's hand, but God's;
and it is not man but God who hangs, tortures, beheads, kills, and
fights. All these are God's work and judgment" (LW,
46, 96). By serving and assisting the office of political
authority with its sword, Christians participate in God's creative
agency. It is often with this sense of ardent participation
in God's creative agency that Luther commends "obedience" in
reference to temporal authority. Furthermore, because God
constitutes political authority, including the sword, "for the
neighbors' good," such authority extends into the great variety of
offices that "arrest, prosecute, execute, and destroy the wicked
and [that] protect, acquit, defend, and save the good"
(LW, 45, 103). Finally, because divinely constituted
political authority exists to serve the neighbors' good, Christians
can even "use their office like anybody else would his trade, as a
means of livelihood" (LW, 45, 103).
[29] We have concentrated so far on how Luther addresses the first
two classic questions posed within the general framework of the
just war tradition up until his time, the pacifism question and the
authority question, about which John the Steadfast asked.
Luther's response typifies the just war tradition.
[30] The Scepter, the Mirror, and Pacific
Partiality. God establishes "the scepter," the old
symbol of just peacemaking, as the wide circumference within which
"the sword" receives its legitimacy. God is partial to the
scepter, prefers the scepter. One might say the scepter is
God's "preferred look" for the divine mask. Luther says things like
this frequently in his writings, though only seldom does he sustain
such an argument.25 Many classic
Christian theologians have known this. Not always have
they emphasized it, to put it mildly. The consequences have
been tragic, sometimes, disastrous. God's partiality for just
peacemaking has not been sufficiently asserted and argued by the
great portion of the church catholic, as Bishop Hanson rightly
points out.
[31] Luther's treatises where he has argued for God's pacific
partiality have not, by a long shot, matched the fame of dozens of
other treatises on different subjects. This speaks more about
his heirs than about him, of course. Here, we'll look at one
treatise and take responsibility to promote it.
[32] Luther's Commentary on Psalm 82 (1530) is a "mirror
of the prince." In this standard genre within Western
literature, a wise and respected person writes a treatise which
functions like a mirror for the ruler in his or her vocation.
Upon waking each morning the ruler looks intently into the mirror
and sees the normative portrait which then daily becomes
him.26 In Luther's
biblically imagined mirror political authority exists for the
public good and thus to honor God.27 "All this is
written because it is God's will to establish and maintain peace
among the children of Adam for their own good" (LW 13,
44). We'll focus on only four characteristic elements that the
public good needs: the accountability of political authority, the
admonitory duty of preachers, and the two-fold criteria of justice
and peacemaking.
Psalm 82
1. God stands in the congregation of God,
And is Judge among the gods.
2. How long will you judge unjustly
And prefer the persons of the godless?
3. Judge the poor and the orphan
And help the wretched and needy to justice.
4. Rescue the small and poor man,
Deliver him out of the hand of the godless
5. But they know nothing and consider nothing,
They go in darkness;
All the foundations of the land must fall.
6. I said, indeed: "You are gods
And all together children of the Highest.
7. But you shall die like men,
And fall like a prince."
8. Arise, O God, and judge the earth,
For Thou dost inherit among the heathen.
[33] Luther considers all the offices of political authority to
be the "gods" of the psalmist's poetic imagination. Luther
links this not only to St. Paul's teaching in Rom. 13:1-4, as he
routinely does, but also to King Jehoshaphat's teaching about
rulers in 2Chron. 19:6: "Consider, what you are doing, for you
judge not on behalf of human beings but on the Lord's behalf; he is
with you in giving judgment." The office of political
authority exercises divine agency in the world and "therefore it is
rightly called a divine thing, godlike, or gods" (LW 13,
44). Political authority's accountability starts with its
divine institution.
[34] Jehoshaphat's teaching does not stop with God's institution
of the office of political authority, and neither does
Luther. As we noted earlier, Luther prohibits rulers from
considering themselves autonomous and doing arbitrarily "whatever
they please." For this reason Jehoshaphat instructs the
"gods" in "the fear of the Lord." "Now, let the fear of the
Lord be upon you [in political office]; take care what you do, for
there is no perversion of justice with the Lord our God, or
partiality, or taking of bribes" (2Chron. 19:7). "The fear of
the Lord" is the biblical trope for accountability.
[35] Luther treats both the rulers and ruled, both the "gods" and
the "congregation," because the psalmist addresses both. He
turns his mirror steadily toward the prince. But neither are the
gods to be proud and self-willed. For they are not gods among
the people and overlords of the congregation in such a way that
they have this position all to themselves and can do as they
like. Not so! God Himself is there also. He will
judge, punish, and correct them; and if they do not obey, they will
not escape. (LW 13, 45) And again: "He keeps
down the rulers, so that they do not abuse His majesty and power
according to their own self-will but use them for that peace for
which He has appointed and preserves them" (ibid.).
[36] God stays firm with political authority precisely because
political communities are "God's congregation." Luther waxes
eloquently with the psalmist.
[37] Observe that he calls all communities or organized
assemblies "the congregation of God," because they are God's own,
and He accepts them as His own work, just as (Jonah 3:3) He
calls Nineveh "a city of God." For He has made, and makes,
all communities. He still brings them together, feeds the,
lets them grow, blesses and preserves them, gives them fields and
meadows, cattle, water, air, sun and moon, and everything they
have, even body and life, as it is written (Gen. 1:29). For
what have we, and what has all the world, that does not come
unceasingly from Him? But even though experience ought to
teach us this, He has to say it in plain words, and openly confess
and boast that the communities are His . . . that a community is
God's creature and His ordinance . . . [and not] come into
existence by accidents, through people holding together and living
side by side in the say way murderers and robbers and other wicked
bands gather to disturb the peace and ordinance of God . . . . But
David know it very well when he says (Ps. 24:1, 2): "The earth is
the Lord's and those who dwell therein; for He has founded it upon
the seas and built it upon the waters"; and his son Solomon says
(Ps. 127:1): "Except God keep house and city, the builder and
the watchman build and watch in vain." . . .
[38] Such communities are God's work, which He daily creates,
supports, and increases, so that they can sit at home and beget
children and educate them. Therefore this word is, in the
first place, a great and pleasant comfort to all those who find
themselves situated in such a community. It assures them that
God accepts them as His work and His creation, cares for them and
protects and supports them, as we can, in fact, see with our own
eyes. . . . For this word "congregation of God" is a precious word
. . . . (LW 13, 46-47)
[39] As we see, God holds authorities accountable for how they
rule because God creates these communities to thrive. But how
will God exercise this accountability? What will be God's
this-worldly media for doing so? Living in the sixteenth
century, Luther doesn't have much of a democratic imagination, at
least not in reference to political communities. There's no
government "of the people, by the people, for the people."
So, how does "the fear of the Lord" happen?
[40] Where, then, is God? Or how do we become sure that
there is a God who thus rebukes? Answer: You hear in
this place that "He stands in the congregation." Where His
congregation is, there you will find Him. For there He has
appointed priests and preachers, to whom He has committed the duty
of teaching, exhorting, rebuking, comforting, in a word, of
preaching the Word of God. (LW 13, 49)
[41] Luther stresses the public character of the admonitory duty
of the preaching office by noting that God "stands."
"Observe, however, that a preacher by whom God rebukes the gods is
to 'stand in the congregation.' He is to 'stand': that is, he
is to be firm and confident and deal uprightly and honestly with
it; and 'in the congregation,' that is, openly and boldly before
God and men" (ibid.). Not surprisingly, Luther does
not withhold criticism for preachers who, when the situation
demands it, do not speak truth to power and do not do it
publicly-the twin sins of "unfaithfulness" and "backbiting."
There are many bishops and preachers in the ministry, but they do not "stand" and serve God faithfully. On the contrary, they lie down or otherwise play with their office. These are the lazy and worthless preachers who do not tell the princes and lords their sins. In some cases they do not notice the sins. They lie down and snore in their office and do nothing that pertains to it except that, like swine, they take up the room where good preachers should stand. These form the great majority. Others, however, play the hypocrite and flatter the wicked gods and strengthen them in their self-will. . . .
The other sin is called backbiting. The whole world is full in every corner of preachers and laymen who bandy evil words about their gods, i.e., princes and lords, curse them, and call them names, though not boldly and in the open, but in corners and in their own sects. But this accomplishes nothing except to make the evil worse. . . .
So, then, this first verse teaches that to rebuke rulers is not seditious, provided it is done in the way here described: namely, by the office to which God has committed that duty, and through God's Word, spoken publicly, boldly, and honestly. To rebuke rulers in this way is, on the contrary a praiseworthy, noble, and rare virtue, and a particularly great service to God, as the psalm here proves. It would be far more seditious if a preacher did not rebuke the sins of the rulers; for then he makes people angry and sullen, strengthens the wickedness of the tyrants, becomes a partaker in it, and bears responsibility for it. Thus God might be angered and might allow rebellion to come as a penalty. The other way-when the lords are rebuked as well as the people, and the people as well as the lords (as the prophets did)-no one can blame anything on the other person. They have to bear with one another, be satisfied, and be at peace with one another. (LW 13, 49-51)
[42] In Luther's account, the psalmist advances three criteria
which shape the office of political authority and underlie
admonition: honor God's Word by allowing it to be freely heard (Ps.
82:2); pursue justice for poor, orphaned, and widowed people (Ps.
82:3); and proliferate peacemaking (Ps. 82:3). We'll look
only at Luther's reflections on the last two, leaving the
complexities of the first criterion for another time.
[43] Luther notes the far-reaching effects of furthering justice
and the cause of the most vulnerable. "For this virtue
includes all the works of righteousness" (LW 13,
53). Establishing laws grounded in justice is like building a
grand hospital.
[44] See now what a hospital such a prince can build! He
needs no stone, no wood, no builders; and he need give neither
endowment nor income. To endow hospitals and help poor people
is, indeed, a precious good work in itself. But when such a
hospital becomes so great that a whole land, and especially the
really poor people of that land, enjoy it, then it is a general,
true, princely, indeed, a heavenly and divine hospital. For only a
few enjoy the first kind of hospital, and sometimes they are false
knaves masquerading as beggars. But the second kind of hospital
comes to the aid only of the really poor, widows, orphans,
travelers, and other forlorn folk. Besides, it preserves rich or
poor, his living and his goods for everyone, so that he does not
have to become a beggar or a poor man. If the law were not kept, no
one could keep anything from another, and all would have to become
beggars together and be ruined and destroyed. However, there are
many who are not beggars and do not become beggars. For them the
overlord is providing in this hospital. For so to help a man that
he does not need to become a beggar is just as much of a good work
and a virtue and an alms as to give to a man and to help a man who
has already become a beggar. (LW 13, 53-54)
[45] Luther calls the psalmists third criterion or virtue
"peacemaking" (LW 13, 55). In his mirror he does not
sharply distinguish peacemaking, which involves primarily making
just laws, from peacekeeping, which involves enforcing these laws
with the sword. Rather, he oscillates between them. But
he's clear on the following point: "Law is wisdom and should
be the first of the two; for government by force without wisdom
does not last" (LW 13, 55). As he does with justice,
Luther stresses the far-reaching effects of peacemaking.
Now, who can recount all the benefits that come from this third virtue? One would first have to tell what the benefits of peace are, and what harm the absence of peace does. But who on earth is so eloquent and so wise that he would undertake to recount the whole of both of these things? . . . I could more easily count the sand on the seashore or the leaves and the blades of grass in the woods. (LW 13, 55-56)
Indeed, "where peace is, there is half a heaven. . . . [L]ack of peace may be counted half a hell, or hell's prelude and beginning" (LW 13, 55).
[46] Luther rounds out his mirror of pacific partiality with the
following:
In a word, after the Gospel or the ministry, there is on earth no better jewel, no greater treasure, nor richer alms, no fairer endowment, no finer possession than a ruler who makes and preserves just laws. Such people are rightly called gods. These are the virtues, the profit, the fruits, and the good works that God has appointed to this rank in life. It is not for nothing that He has called them gods; and it is not His will that it shall be a lazy, empty, idle estate, in which people seek only honor, power, luxury, selfish profit, and self-will. He would have them full of great, innumerable, unspeakable good works, so that they may be partakers of His divine majesty and help Him to do divine and superhuman works. (LW 13, 54-55)
[47] In his Large Catechism Luther memorably recommends a breadloaf as the preferential symbol of political authority. "It would therefore be fitting if the coat of arms of every upright prince were emblazoned with a loaf of bread instead of a lion."28 In short, God would have political authority proliferate just peacemaking. In fact, God would have countless vocations proliferate just peacemaking.29
III. Pacific Proliferation.
[48] Surely, the "breadloaf's" time has come! What does this
mean? It means that Lutheran convictions commit us to
enlarging just peacemaking as the comprehensive
environment for the just peacekeeping that just war
tradition also recognizes as necessary but never, never sufficient
or preferred. Just peacemaking characterizes the Lutheran
normative default conviction and commitment. Pacific
proliferation always starts and ends in just peacemaking. In
fact, proliferation will happen among us to the extent that
peacemaking practices permeate us. Five things will help
Lutherans imagine a more unified pacific theory and practice.
[49] First, Lutherans can learn much from historic pacifist
traditions. The varieties of the pacifist tradition have
practiced expertise in just peacemaking. "Pacifism is a
complex and subtle range of value positions on morality, peace, and
war, not the stereotyped extreme of conventional wisdom. The
varieties of pacifism have emerged within a just-warist value
tradition, to some degree building on and extending that
tradition."30 Pacifism in each
variety has two sides: the "critical" side and the "positive"
side. The critical side, for instance in "principled
pacifism," stands for "no war, no violence, no sword, by anyone
under any circumstances." Pacifism's positive side means "to
work tirelessly, vigorously, and endlessly for the establishment of
peace normed by justice." On the one hand, Lutherans,
honoring the just war tradition, will not adopt the critical side
of pacifism. This has most often been the primary, even only,
topic of conversation between the just war tradition and the
variety of pacifist traditions. On the other hand, Lutherans
have every reason in the world to honor and be allied with the
historic pacifist traditions-represented, for example, by
Mennonites and Quakers-as they have developed and practiced the
positive side of just peacemaking.
[50] Twenty-five researchers-Christian ethicists, biblical and
moral theologians, peace activists, conflict resolution
practitioners, and international relations scholars-have initiated
a discussion of just peacemaking theory and practice across the
more established paradigms of pacifist traditions and just war
tradition.31 They have
developed an initial road map of ten broad practices: support
nonviolent direct action; take independent initiatives to reduce
threat; use cooperative conflict resolution; acknowledge
responsibility for conflict and injustice and seek repentance and
forgiveness; advance democracy, human rights, and religious
liberty; foster just and sustainable economic development; work
with emerging cooperative forces in the international system;
strengthen the United Nations and international efforts for
cooperation and human rights; reduce offensive weapons and weapons
trade; and encourage grassroots peacemaking groups and voluntary
associations. These are fruitful directions.
[51] Second, the pacific mandate requires sapiential roots.
The time has come for Lutherans to recover in a vigorous way our
sapiential conviction. That is, in God's left-hand ruling of
the world we must take "account of worldly wisdom," as Luther puts
it in another of his "mirrors for the prince."32 These are
complex issues that need careful attention today. Lutherans
shirk them, which we're doing, at our peril. With his vibrant
doctrine of God's twofold ruling of the one world Luther rebuffed a
slide toward Christian theocracy.
To be sure, God made the secular government subordinate and subject to reason, because it is to have no jurisdiction over the welfare of souls or things of eternal value but only over physical and temporal goods, which God places under human dominion, Genesis 2:8ff. For this reason nothing is taught in the Gospel about how it is to be maintained and regulated, except that the Gospel bids people honor it and not oppose it. Therefore the heathen can speak and teach about this very well, as they have done. . . . God is a gentle and wealthy Lord. He casts much gold, silver, wealth, dominions, and kingdoms among the godless, as though it were chaff or sand. Thus He casts great intelligence, wisdom, languages, and oratorical ability among them, too, so that [at times] His dear Christians look like mere children, fools, and beggars by comparison. . . . Those who set down the law had to be experienced in big deals and to be familiar with the thinking of many people; for this they had been endowed with a high degree of intelligence and brains. . . . Therefore, whoever wants to learn and become wise in secular government, let him read the heathen books and writings. They have truly painted it and portrayed it quite beautifully and generously, with both verses and pictures, with teachings and examples; and they became the source for the ancient imperial laws. I am convinced that God gave and preserved such heathen books as those of the poets and the histories, like Homer, Virgil, Demosthenes, Cicero, Livy, and afterwards the fine old jurists-as He has also given and preserved other temporal goods among the heathen and godless at all times-that the heathen and godless too might have their prophets, apostles, and theologians or preachers for the secular government. (LW 13, 198-199)
Historically, Lutherans, following Luther, have called such
convictions natural law moral reasoning. With the
re-emergence of Christian theocracy in our own time and place we
would do well to develop a critical realist account of natural law
moral reasoning. Lutherans are overdue here.
[52] Third, the public work of justice gains wisdom and legitimacy
when solidly rooted in works of mercy. Lutherans have
historic, rich experience and expertise in the traditional six
works of mercy of Matt. 25: feeding the hungry, quenching the
thirsty, welcoming the stranger, clothing the naked, healing the
sick, and befriending the imprisoned. Now is the time to
reconnect Lutheran congregations to this history. I'm
thinking now about Lutheran Services in America
(LSA).33
[53] Nearly three hundred social ministry organizations make up
LSA. It represents nearly $10 billion in annual
revenue. This makes LSA the largest civil society
organization in the United States. The National Council of
YMCAs is second at under $5 billion; American Red Cross, Catholic
Charities USA, United Jewish Communities, Goodwill Industries
International, and Salvation Army all come in at $2-3 billion in
that order.
[54] Lutheran congregations have on the whole lost track of this
story. What a tragedy! This heritage even originated,
by and large, in the very congregations that now suffer the
amnesia. It's not hopeless, however. LSA's first
mission policy/desired outcome is "valued identity-being Lutheran
in social ministry is identifiable, valued and supported by social
ministry organizations, church bodies, and communities." LSA
itself can build this valued identity by collaborating with
Lutheran congregations in meaningful, concrete ways. This
will also incite the mercy work of congregations.
[55] As works of mercy expand, congregations will also enlarge
their imagination for works of justice. Another of LSA's five
mission policies/desired outcomes is a "unified voice-Lutheran
social ministry organizations have an effective voice for service
and justice to church, to government and to society." Mutual
collaboration will expand both mercy and justices
ministries-indeed, each through the other. Further, public
policy makers more readily attend to calls for justice when they
are infused with a moral epistemology rooted in genuine works of
mercy. These kinds of collaborations will help Lutherans
"step forward as a public church," the third of five strategic
directions of the ELCA.34 Best of all, of
course, neighbors needing mercy and justice will get both, and thus
enlarge their participation in the well-being of God's world.
[56] Fourth, what the world needs now is publicity, sweet
publicity. More than ever just peacemaking in our time
entails profound publicity. By "publicity" I do not mean public
relations. Far from it! "Publicity" entails sturdy
accountability to wider publics, to other nations as well as to the
rapidly emerging publics of global civil society. I propose
adding "publicity" to the ten peacemaking practices listed
earlier. Publicity could be considered part of one or two of
the others. But, it deserves room of its own! It's that
crucial to just peacemaking.
[57] Without repeating what I've recently written in this journal
about publicity, let me say this much here.35 Democracy, both
as idea and as practice, stands at a crossroads today. A
critical theory of democracy distinguishes three basic forms of
democracy: liberal, aristocratic, and deliberative. The
differences matter. I've argued elsewhere for deliberative
democracy and its practices. Publicity is a key
hermeneutic of deliberative democratic practices. As public
accountability publicity entails moral vigilance within nations and
among nations. It entails the moral vigilance provided by
international institutions and especially by global civil
society. And, moral vigilance contributes to the
effectiveness of civic international publicity. Now's the
time to count the ways that world Christianity has been hearing a
call from God to vocations of civic international publicity.
Now's the time to multiply those vocations. The pacific
mandates practicing publicity.
[58] Fifth, I nominate prayer as a twelfth peacemaking
practice. In fact, the previous eleven find their source and
their summary in prayer. The close encounter between prayer
and publicity especially deserves serious attention, which must
wait for another day. The pacific itself mandates
prayer.
End Notes
1 Mark Hanson, "President's Address," at http://www.lutheranworld.org/LWF_Documents/2004-Council/President_Address_EN.pdf
2 There are good reasons, though I won't explore them here, for not using the notion of "principles" regarding the just war tradition.
3 Robert Kolb and Timothy J. Wengert, eds., The Book of Concord: The Confessions of the Evangelical Lutheran Church, trans. Charles Arand, et al (Minneapolis: Fortress, 2000), Confessio Augustana XVI:1-2, p. 49.
4 Here, I will not go into the specific criteria of the just war tradition. For brief, accessible primers on the basics of just war theory see James Turner Johnson, "Just War," in The Westminster Dictionary of Christian Ethics, eds. J. Childress & J. Macquarrie (Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1986); also A. F. Holmes, "Just-War Theory," in New Dictionary of Christian Ethics and Pastoral Theology, eds., D. Atkinson et al. (Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 1995). For thorough standard accounts of just war tradition see Paul Ramsey, The Just War (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1968); Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument with Historical Illustrations (New York: Basic Books, 1977; James Turner Johnson, Just War Tradition and the Restraint of War: A Moral and Historical Inquiry (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1981).
5 For my own description and analysis of the just war tradition and its criteria for engaging in war see "Puckering up for Postmodern Kissing: Civil Society and the Lutheran Entwinement of Just Peace/Just War" and "Congregational Strategies for Invigorating Lutheranism's Just PeaceMaking Tradition" both in Journal of Lutheran Ethics, and "'Thou Shalt Not Kill'-The First Commandment of the Just War Tradition," in The Ten Commandments: The Reciprocity of Faithfulness, ed. William Brown (Louisville, KY: Westminster John Knox Press, 2004), pp. 248-265.
6 Kolb and Wengert, p. 410. Strictly speaking according to Luther, we would have to consider "thou shalt not kill" as the second commandment of the just war tradition. Luther establishes "thou shalt have no other gods before me" as the first commandment of each of the other nine.
7 In Luther's Works, American Edition, 55 vols. (Philadelphia: Fortress Press; St. Louis: Concordia Publishing House, 1955-1986), 46 (hereafter LW). The United States Conference of Catholic Bishops has rightly noted that the just war tradition entails a "strong presumption against the use of force"; see The Harvest of Justice Is Sown in Peace, (United States Conference of Catholic Bishops, 1993), at http://www.usccb.org/sdwp/harvest.shtml
8 Here, I cannot enter into the debate regarding what has become something like "the standard account." In this account Jesus was a political pacifist and so was the church of the first three centuries. Then came the Constantinian compromise of the just war. The progressive slide away from pacifism continued into the era of holy war-crusade. Roland Bainton is the most noteworthy proponent of this telling (see Christian Attitudes toward War and Peace (New York: Abingdon Press, 1960)), which has taken hold not only within pacifist traditions but also within the mainstreams of the just war tradition. James Turner Johnson has undertaken an extensive study and concluded, "The problem is that this [now standard] account of early Christian history is both dead wrong and misleading in its depiction of the historical evidence" (see The Quest for Peace (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1987), p. 9). Johnson finds rudimentary just war arguments and attitudes at least one hundred and fifty years prior to Constantine thus forestalling a "convenient scapegoat like Constantine to [be the] blame for the alleged loss of moral purity in the Church's attitude to war and the military" (p. 15).
9 Patrologia Graeca, Migne, 26.1173 (translation provided by Louis Swift, The Early Fathers on War and Military Service (Wilmington, DE: Michael Glazier, 1983), p. 95.
10 One notable place where Augustine treats the relationship between God's "not kill" command and justifiable war is in The City of God 1.21(New York: Fathers of the Church, volume 8, 1950). Thomas Aquinas's treatment of just war within the context of God's "not kill" command can be found in The Commandments of God: Conferences on the Two Precepts of Charity and the Ten Commandments (London: Burns Oates & Washbourne, 1937), pp. 57-58 and in Summa Theologica 2-2.64.3-4. It is now common for contemporary theologians to raise the question of just war when treating the ten commandments. For examples, see Walter J. Harrelson, The Ten Commandments and Human Rights, revised edition (Macon, GA: Mercer University Press, 1997), p. 92; Paul L. Lehmann, The Decalogue and a Human Future (Grand Rapids, MI, 1995) p. 165; Terrence Fretheim, Exodus (Louisville, KY: 1991), pp. 232-234; Jan Lochman, Signposts to Freedom: The Ten Commandments and Christian Faith (Minneapolis, MN: Augsburg, 1982), pp.104; William Barclay, The Ten Commandments for Today (New York: Harper & Row, 1973), PP. 78-93
11 Augustine, op. cit. For an excellent overview of the relevant issues in Augustine, Aquinas, and Calvin, see Lisa Sowle Cahill, Love Your Enemies: Discipleship, Pacifism, and Just War Theory (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1994), pp. 55-118.
12 Aquinas, Summa Theologica 2-2.64.6
13 Kolb and Wengert, p. 352.
14 Ibid., p. 412. John Calvin also says it elegantly: [I]n negative precepts, as hey are called, the opposite affirmation is also to be understood; else it would not be by any means consistent, that a person would satisfy God's Law by merely abstaining form doing injury to others. . . . Nay, natural common sense demands more than that we should abstain form wrong-doing. And, not to say more on this point, it will plainly appear from the summary of the Second Table, that God not only forbids us to be murderers, but also prescribes that every one should study faithfully to defend the life of his neighbor, and practically to declare that it is dear to him; for in that summary no mere negative phrase is used, but the words expressly set forth that our neighbors are to be loved. It is unquestionable, then, that of those whom God there commands to be loved, He here commends the lives to our care.
See John Calvin, Commentaries on the Four Last Books of Moses Arranged in the Form of a Harmony, vol. 3, trans. Charles W. Bingham (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1950), p. 20-21.
15 See Luther, Commentary on Psalm 1, LW 14, 296. Terrence Fretheim observes that the negative form is "pertinent" in that the commandments "focus on the outer limits of conduct rather than specific behaviors. . . . Yet the commands implicitly commend their positive side. . . . There is a certain comprehensiveness in their ties to a considerable range of life experience . . . ." See Terrence Fretheim, Exodus in Interpretation: A Bible Commentary for Teaching and Preaching, ed., J. Mays (Louisville: John Knox Press, 1991), p. 221. Karl Barth, borrowing Albert Schweitzer's phrase, interprets the "not kill" first under "respect [reverence] for life" and only then under "protection of life." See Karl Barth, Church Dogmatics (Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1957), 3.4:324 -397. Walter Harrelson notes the "sweeping generality" of this commandment, "surprising in its scope." See Walter J. Harrelson, The Ten Commandments and Human Rights, revised edition (Macon, GA: Mercer University Press, 1997), p. 89.
16 I analyze of the last two points in Simpson, "'Thou Shalt Not Kill'" pp. 257-262.
17 For my account of Luther's critical theology of political authority see Gary M. Simpson, "Toward a Lutheran 'Delight in the Law of the Lord': Church and State in the Context of Civil Society," in Church and State: Lutheran Perspectives, eds. John Stumme and Robert Tuttle (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 2003), pp. 20-50.
18 "The sword" was that synechdochal figure of speech commonly used in Luther's day to refer to political authority's coercive power.
19 Here Luther is following Augustine in, for example, Reply to Faustus the Manichean, vol. IV, The Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, First Series, ed. Philip Schaff (Buffalo: Christian Literature Co., 1887), 22.71-76, pp. 299-302. Aquinas also follows Augustine here (see Summa Theological 2-2.40.1). In reference to the Ten Commandments Luther locates political authority within the purview of "Honor thy father and thy mother." See my "Toward a Lutheran 'Delight in the Law of the Lord,'" pp. 26-29.
20 See Gerhard Ebeling, Word and Faith (Philadelphia: Fortress, 1963), 73-74.
21 Of course Luther invariably knows that because the old Adam always clings to this life, he is describing Christians qua Christian, that is, "to the extent that he is a Christian" (LW, 26, 134). See also, for example, Luther's reflections on baptism and holy communion in the Large Catechism (Kolb and Wengert, pp. 456-480). In Temporal Authority Luther also takes up the second, theological or spiritual use of the law, whereby the Holy Spirit convicts of sin and drives to Christ. But the spiritual use of the law is not our primary concern in this inquiry.
22 For a noteworthy interpretation of Luther's teaching of two kingdoms and two regiments see William H. Lazareth, Christians in Society: Luther, the Bible, and Social Ethics (Minneapolis, MN: Fortress Press, 2001).
23 See Augustine, "Letter 189 To Boniface," Saint Augustine: Letters, vol. 4 (165-203), trans. Wilfrid Parsons, SND, vol. 30 of The Fathers of the Church, ed. Roy J. Deferrari (New York: Fathers of the Church, Inc., 1951), p. 269).
24 This distinction is ubiquitous in Luther's theological and ethical reflection. See, for instance, Temporal Authority (LW, 45, 95-96, 101, 103, et al). Besides Scripture itself, it's likely that Augustine tutors Luther on the distinction between for self/for other (see Augustine, "Letter 47 To Publicola," Saint Augustine: Letters, vol. 1 (1-82), trans. Wilfrid Parsons, SND, vol. 12 of The Fathers of the Church, ed. Roy J. Deferrari (New York: Fathers of the Church, Inc., 1951), p. 230). Likewise, Ambrose tutors Augustine (see On the Duties of the Clergy, 3.3.23 in St. Ambrose: Select Works and Letters, eds. Philip Schaff and Henry Wace, vol. 10 of Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, second series, (New York: Christian Literature Co., 1896), p. 71). It's Ambrose, in fact, who bequeaths to Augustine the distinction between just and unjust war (see Ambrose, op. cit., 1.35.176-177).
25 For Luther on the scepter see LW 12, 236-247.
26 LW 13, 142-172. The most famous "mirror of the prince" is Niccolo Machiavelli's The Prince, written within a decade of Luther's and in sharp contrast.
27 "For, in Scripture, to have a long life means not merely to grow old but to have everything that belongs to life-for example, health, spouse and children, sustenance, peace, good government, etc., without which this life cannot be enjoyed nor will long endure." In his catechisms Luther locates political authority within the Fourth Commandment (see Kolb and Wengert).
28 Fourth Petition of the Lord's Prayer in the Large Catechism (Kolb and Wengert, pp. 450-451).
29 Gustav Wingren's warning is noteworthy at this point. He trenchantly criticizes interpreters who reduce Luther's notion of the civil use of the law to merely "an association with politics," which Luther himself sometimes did (Creation and Law (Philadelphia: Muhlenberg Press, 1961), p. 153).
30 Robert Phillips and Duane Cady, Humanitarian Intervention: Just War vs. Pacifism (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 1996), pp. 32-33. For other expositions of the varieties of pacifism see John Howard Yoder, Nevertheless: The Varieties and Shortcomings of Religious Pacifism (Scottsdale, PA: Herald Press, 1992); also Edward LeRoy Long, Jr., War and Conscience in America (Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1968).
31 See Glen Stassen, ed., Just Peacemaking: Ten Practices for Abolishing War (Cleveland: Pilgrim Press, 1998). "Abolishing" in the subtitle is not, however, the right category. Also see Jeffrey Gros & John Rempel, eds., The Fragmentation of the Church and Its Unity in Peacemaking (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 2001).
32 See Luther, Commentary on Psalm 101 in LW 13, 199.
33 For Lutheran Services in America see www.lutheranservices.org. For the comparative revenue cited in the following paragraph see Nonprofit Times November 1, 2002.
34 For the ELCA's strategic directives go to www.elca.org.
35 Gary M. Simpson, "Hope in the Face of the National
Security Strategy: Three Readings and Patriotic Publicity," Journal
of Lutheran Ethics 5.5 (May 2005) at http://www.elca.org/jle/article.asp?k=529.
Also see Simpson, "Hope in the Face of Empire: Failed Patriotism,
Civic International Publicity, and Patriotic Peacebuilding," Word
& World 25 (Spring 2005):127-138.
© June 2005
Journal of Lutheran Ethics
Volume 5, Issue 6